Saturday, July 12, 2014

Shelby v. Holder: Dismantling the Rationale of the Voting Rights Act's Affirmative Action and its Majority-Minority Districts


                                                                                                         William M. Leiter
                                   Notice: This post is accessible by using  Windows 7 or higher.
Affirmative Action and its Thesis of White Venom
Affirmative action differs from other antidiscrimination initiatives in that (1) it targets and seeks to remedy White systemic societal bias (as manifested in public and private illegal discrimination), not individual malefactors; (2) it mandates race, ethnic, gender, disability-conscious remedies for the disproportionately-adverse effects -- the so-called disparate impact -- of venomous societal discrimination affecting protected groups, whether or not specific discriminatory intent on the part of individual defendants can be isolated; and (3) it seeks to integrate institutions by race, ethnicity, disabled condition, and sex by providing the same proportional benefits available to non-minorities. Race/ethnic affirmative-action objectives have been actively pursued by the Obama Administration and its predecessors in their implementation  of the 1965 Voting Rights Act (VRA).[3] During the Obama years, however, the rationale for the VRA’s affirmative-action regulations, namely that White systemic antiminority-animus  badly undercuts minority voting and its effectiveness, was rejected by the Supreme Court in Shelby County v. Holder[4] where a slim majority of five insisted that America has cast off its historic antiminority venom preventing Black/Hispanic participation in voting and office-holding. That view was rejected in a sometimes anguished dissent by four members of the High Court.
The VRA’s Coverage/Preclearance Formula and its Abolition in Shelby v. Holder
            At the onset of the VRA in 1965, its Section 4 abolished literacy tests and other such devices (e.g., good character and knowledge tests and character vouching by other citizens) as  preonditions for voting in states and/or their political subdisions where fewer than 50% of the voting-age population was registered to vote or voted for president in the 1964 election.  The former Confederate States of Alabama, Georgia, Louisianna, Mississippi, South Carolina, Virginia, and 39 North Carolina counties were targeted by this coverage formula, and were consequently required--by Section 5 of the VRA-- to preclear any changes in voting procedures with either the U.S. attorney general, or a special three-membered U.S. District Court located in the District of Columbia. By an amendment to VRA’s Section 4 in 1970, the test abolition and preclearance /coverage formula applicable to the former Confederate areas was extended to states and their political subdivision where less than 50% of the voting-age population was registered or voted in the 1968 presidential election. In this way, several counties in California, New Hampshire, and New York became subject to preclearance. Congress in 1970 also abolished literacy tests and other such devices as preconditions for voting nationwide. This nationwide prohibition was made permanent in 1975 when Congress also promulgated other VRA-Section 4 amendments: preclearance was extended to states/political subdivisions where fewer than 50% of the voting-age population was registered to vote or voted for president in 1972; preclearance was also extended to those political divisions where English-only voting materials were provided and where over 5% of the voting-age citizens spoke a single language other than English. As a result of these 1975 amendments,  Alaska, Arizona, Texas and several counties in California, Florida, Michigan, New York, North Carolina, and South Dakota were required to preclear voting changes. Additionally in 1975, Congress forbade voting discrimination based on language-minority status to correspond to VRA’s ban on race or color discrimination.[5]  
            The preclearance/coverage formula of VRA’s Section 4 was found unconstitutional in Shelby County v. Holder (2013).[6] That Section’s affirmative-action assumption that various areas of the country were --because of voter turnout/registration--systemically and particularly prone to pursue prohibited racial/ethnic voting discrimination was found by the Supreme Court to be outdated. “Our country has changed,” the Supreme Court’s majority opinion insisted, “and while any racial discrimination in voting is too much, Congress must ensure that the legislation it passes to remedy that problem speaks to current conditions.” [7] The coverage/preclearance dimension of Section 4 does not conform with the country’s current racial/ethnic conditions and attitudes, especially those in the former Confederate areas where White supremacy was most emphasized. Central portions of the Shelby majoritiy opinion follow:[8]
Nearly 50 years …[since the passage of the VRA], things have changed dramatically. … In the covered jurisdictions,"[v]oter turnout and registration rates now approach parity. Blatantly discriminatory evasions of federal decrees are rare. And minority candidates hold office at unprecedented levels." The tests and devices that blocked access to the ballot have been forbidden nationwide for over 40 years.
Those conclusions are not ours alone. Congress said the same when it reauthorized the Act in 2006, writing that "[s]ignificant progress has been made in eliminating first generation barriers experienced by minority voters, including increased numbers of registered minority voters, minority voter turnout, and minority representation in Congress, State legislatures, and local elected offices." The House Report elaborated that "the number of African-Americans who are registered and who turn out to cast ballots has increased significantly over the last 40 years, particularly since 1982," and noted that "[i]n some circumstances, minorities register to vote and cast ballots at levels that surpass those of white voters." That Report also explained that there have been "significant increases in the number of African-Americans serving in elected offices"; more specifically, there has been approximately a 1,000 percent increase since 1965 in the number of African-American elected officials in the six States originally covered by the Voting Rights Act.
The following chart, compiled from the Senate and House Reports, compares voter registration numbers from 1965 to those from 2004 in the six originally covered States. These are the numbers that were before Congress when it reauthorized the Act in 2006:

1965
2004

White
Black
Gap
White
Black
Gap
Alabama
69.2
19.3
49.9
73.8
72.9
 0.9
Georgia
 62.[6]
27.4
35.2
63.5
64.2
-0.7
Louisiana
80.5
31.6
48.9
75.1
71.1
 4.0
Mississippi
69.9
 6.7
63.2
72.3
76.1
-3.8
South Carolina
75.7
37.3
38.4
74.4
71.1
 3.3
Virginia
61.1
38.3
22.8
68.2
57.4
10.8
The 2004 figures come from the Census Bureau. Census Bureau data from the most recent election indicate that African-American voter turnout exceeded white voter turnout in five of the six States originally covered by §5, with a gap in the sixth State of less than one half of one percent. The preclearance statistics are also illuminating. In the first decade after enactment of §5, the Attorney General objected to 14.2 percent of proposed voting changes. In the last decade before reenactment, the Attorney General objected to a mere 0.16 percent.
       
            It should be restated that the VRA literacy test abolition, preclearance, and language-minority protection were the outgrowth of notions of pervasive White systemic discrimination, and not the demonstration of intentional racism by any particular VRA-covered area affecting individuals who did not vote. The VRA assumption was that low turnout resulted from systemic racial and ethnic discrimination pulsating within the societies subject to VRA requirements.  Congress extended this notion of White systemic discrimination nationally when it abolished literacy tests countrywide in 1970 and again in 1975.
The Obama Administration and VRA’s Section 5[9]
As noted, covered jurisdictions under Section 4 of the VRA are required by Section 5 to submit changes in voting procedures for federal preclearance. Voting changes, under the initial statute, “could not have the purpose and will not have the effect of denying or abridging the right to vote on account of race or color….”[10] In 1969, the Supreme Court, in Allen v. State Board of Elections[11] interpreted denial/abridgment of the right to vote to incorporate any voting change diluting the right to an effective vote.[12] Allen's extremely broad ruling established that all arguable electoral changes must be submitted for preclearance. In administering the "effect" prong of Section 5's purpose/effect test, the U.S. Department of Justice (DOJ) acted on the affirmative-action premise that the Voting Rights Act's ultimate objective was not merely to pry open the doors of the voting booth, but also to help minorities elect minority candidates, and that race/ethnic‑based districting was the sine qua non of fair minority representation, and the means of remedying the systemic-societal discrimination which gave rise to the African-American historic inability to elect Black officials.[13]  Early on, DOJ's preclearance policy was to withhold approval of potentially discriminatory redistricting plans unless the redistricters agreed to include some form of majority‑minority districting.[14]  By the mid‑1970s, it was common practice to include one or more "super" majority‑minority districts (65 percent or more) in new districting plans in order to pass preclearance scrutiny.[15] Although this antidilution program was initiated under the preclearance provisions of VRA Section 5, since 1982 it has been conducted largely under amended VRA Section 2. From the beginning, race‑based districting has applied to Latino groups as well as African Americans,[16] with the goal, in Abigail Thernstrom’s persuasive view, of achieving minority elected officials proportionate to their population size without the need to prove invidious anti-minority animosity[17]—a goal to which the Obama Administration is committed.
 In his exultation over Section 5 of the VRA’s[18] preclearance role in the creation of controversial majority-minority legislative districts designed to elect minorities, President Obama’s Attorney General Holder coupled the making of these districts with other civil rights laws. These efforts, the Attorney General noted, have opened doors to previously excluded groups, “helping to ensure equal access to schools and public spaces, to restaurants and workplaces, and – perhaps most important of all – to the ballot box.  Our great nation was transformed.”[19] " We are a better nation now than we were because more people are involved in the electoral process. The beauty of this nation, the strength of this nation, is its diversity, and when we try to exclude people from being involved in the process . . . we weaken the fabric of this country.''[20]
            Attorney General Holder along with his former Assistant Attorney General, the head of the Department of Justice’s Civil Rights Division (responsible for the VRA’s implementation), have referred to Section 5 as the “keystone” of the Voting Rights Act.[21] Pertinent provisions of the current Section (amended in 2006)[22] regarding preclearance for covered jurisdictions are:
 (b) Any voting qualification or prerequisite to voting, or standard, practice, or procedure with respect to voting that has the purpose of or will have the effect of diminishing the ability of any citizens of the United States on account of race or color… to elect their preferred candidates of choice denies or abridges the right to vote ….

(c) The term “purpose” in … this section shall include any discriminatory purpose.

(d) The purpose of subsection (b) of this section is to protect the ability of such citizens to elect their preferred candidates of choice.

            As of 2012, the salient/nationally-publicized[23] Section 5 undertakings of the Obama DOJ were preclearance rejections of the voter ID requirements of South Carolina and Texas, the objection to Kinston, North Carolina’s adoption of nonpartisan elections; and the DOJ’s argument against Texas’ legislative redistricting proposal submitted by that State to the District of Columbia’s U.S. District Court. When the U.S. Supreme Court consented to evaluate the constitutionality of Section 5, the Department of Justice vigorously defended it.
            As we have seen, before its nullification in Shelby County  v. Holder, Section 5 authorized preclearance denial when it was determined that either prong of the purpose/effect was violated. In the case of the Texas and South Carolina voter ID laws, the Attorney General concluded, in true statistical affirmative-action fashion, that the effect of the state identification requirements disproportionately burdened protected minorities, and retrogressively diminished their ability to elect persons of their choice. The purpose/intent prong was not addressed. Rejection letters sent to these States on behalf of the Attorney General included the following: 
South Carolina--
When disaggregated by race, the state’s data show that 8.4% of white registered voters lacked any form of DMV-issued ID, as compared to 10.0% of non-white registered voters. In other words, according to the state’s data, which compare the available data in the state’s voter registration database with the available data in the state’s DMV database, minority registered voters were nearly 20% more likely to lack DMV-issued ID than white registered voters, and thus to be effectively disenfranchised by Act R54’s new requirements. We note that the voter registration data matched against the DMV database, and provided to us by the state, does not include several categories of existing registered voters listed as inactive voters,  and hence, the number of registered voters without DMV-issued ID may well be higher than even these numbers suggest….Because we conclude that the state has failed to meet   its burden of demonstrating that section 5 of Act R54 will not have a retrogressive effect, we do not make any determination as to whether the state has established that the proposed changes to its voter identification requirements were adopted with no discriminatory purpose.[24]
 

Texas--
 [A]ccording to the state's own data, a Hispanic registered voter is at least 46.5 percent, and potentially 120.0 percent, more likely than a non-Hispanic registered voter to lack this identification. Even using the data most favorable to the state, Hispanics disproportionately lack either a driver's license or a personal identification card issued by [the Department of Public Safety], and that disparity is statistically significant…. In conclusion, the state has not met its burden of proving that …the proposed [voter identification] requirement will not have a retrogressive effect, or that any specific features of the proposed law will prevent or mitigate that retrogression. Additionally, the state has failed to   demonstrate why it could not meet its stated goals of ensuring electoral   integrity and deterring ineligible voters from voting in a manner that would have avoided this retrogressive effect. Because we conclude that the state has failed to meet its burden of demonstrating that the proposed law will not have a retrogressive effect, we do not make any determination as to whether the   state has established that the proposed changes were adopted with no discriminatory purpose.[25] 

Recall that amended Section 5 proclaimed that any voting procedure which “has the purpose of or will have the effect of diminishing the ability of any citizens of the United States on account of race or color… to elect their preferred candidates of choice denies or abridges the right to vote ….” This dictate required DOJ’s Civil Rights Division (CRD) to make race/ethnic-conscious evaluations as to whether redistricting proposals from covered jurisdictions diminish the ability of protected minorities to elect candidates of their choice. The Obama CRD noted, in its Guidance to nonfederal governments on the matter,[26] that its determinations will be rooted in a consideration of “benchmark” districts (i.e., those associated with the year 2000 CRD-approved districts), and whether race/ethnic benchmark capacity to elect has been denigrated. A multidimensional analysis was to be undertaken including an investigation of apportionment history; population increase/decrease/shifts; and statements of officials concerned with district shaping. Under its standards, CRD approval was not to be restricted to majority-minority districting for ability-to-elect districts can consist of a coalition of minority groups. But, clearly, it would have been a breach of Section 5 for CRD to disapprove of existing majority-minority districts where population stability existed. Majority-minority districts have been, in large part, responsible for the dramatic increase in minority elected officials.[27]Of course CRD has been given enormous discretion in determining what makes an “ability to elect preferred-candidate district.” The law does not provide a specific methodology. However, a prominent student of Section 5--Professor Nathan Persily of Columbia-- reported that his initial survey of the Obama redistricting process indicated that “the practices of the DOJ either since 2006 or since 2008 do not seem, at first blush, to be systematically different than those of earlier years.”[28]
            The Obama DOJ challenged the recent Texas legislative redistricting plan when that plan was submitted to the D.C. District Court for preclearance. Texas had gained four congressional seats resulting from a population increase reported in the 2010 decennial census. Most of this population increase was Hispanic, but, to the DOJ, no additional Hispanic ability-to-elect districts had been created by the Republican-dominated Texas legislature--thus having the effect of diminishing Hispanic capacity to choose a preferred candidate. Likewise, the new Texas plan had moved low-turnout Hispanics into some districts, while moving high-turnout Hispanics into other districts, thus, according to DOJ, showing a purpose to discriminate on the basis of ethnicity.[29] But one person’s purpose to discriminate improperly is another person’s appropriate quest for partisan advantage, and no law can take politics out of politics. How to distinguish the two in the redistricting process is a most difficult if not impossible task.  
Another salient DOJ preclearance rejection of considerable notoriety concerned Kinston, North Carolina, a community with a Black majority population which had voted to adopt a nonpartisan ballot for local elections. The rejection (later withdrawn unceremoniously) cited that the absence of a Democratic ballot label could impede White crossover voting for a Black because African-American candidates are typically Democrats, and a Democratic label could provide helpful policy cues for White Democrats to vote for an African American typically the preferred candidate of the Black community. And crossover Democratic White votes were deemed by the DOJ to be critical to the election of Blacks. Nonpartisanship, once the darling of American Progressives, consequently diminished the capacity of Kinston’s Black population to select preferred Black candidates.[30]
VRA’s Section 2[31]
Section 2 of the VRA, formally unaffected by Shelby County v. Holder, remains  an Obama Administration vehicle for pursuing voting-rights affirmative action--along with its assumption of societally-systemic antiminority views-- as it is currently doing in connection with the redistricting and voter ID issues in Texas mentioned above.[32] Pertinent segments of Section 2 follow:
(a) No voting qualification or prerequisite to voting or standard, practice, or procedure shall be imposed or applied by any State or political subdivision in a manner which results in a denial or abridgement of the right of any citizen of the United States to vote on account of race or color… , as provided in subsection (b) of this section.
(b) A violation of subsection (a) of this section is established if, based on the totality of circumstances, it is shown that the political processes leading to nomination or election in the State or political subdivision are not equally open to participation by members of a class of citizens protected by subsection (a) of this section in that its members have less opportunity than other members of the electorate to participate in the political process and to elect representatives of their choice. The extent to which members of a protected class have been elected to office in the State or political subdivision is one circumstance which may be considered: Provided, That nothing in this section establishes a right to have members of a protected class elected in numbers equal to their proportion in the population.

Section 2’s results test is comparable to the effects dimension of affirmative-action’s disparate-impact theory, seeking the elimination of systemic animosities towards racial/ethnic groups which according to the Shelby County  v. Holder (2013) opinion has evaporated insofar as minority voting rights are concerned. Are then the affirmative-action dimensions of Section 2 still constitutionally viable? With that question in mind it must be noted that the application of the results test in Section 2 has led to the DOJ-aided and abetted creation of majority-minority legislative districts designed--and successfully so-- to elect minorities. The judicial guidepost prompting this districting profusion was crafted by a Supreme Court opinion, Thornburg v. Gingles (1986).[33] 
In setting an evidentiary standard to determine whether, as a result of districting construction, minorities “have less opportunity than other members of the electorate to participate in the political process and to elect representatives of their choice,” the Gingles Court majority employed two standards: the level of minority electoral success, and the extent of racial bloc voting.[34] As Justice Brennan said in the majority opinion:
The essence of a Section 2 claim is that a certain electoral law, practice or structure interacts with social and historical conditions to cause an inequality in the opportunities enjoyed by Black and white voters to elect their preferred representatives.…[M]ultimember districts and at‑large voting schemes "may operate to minimize or cancel out the voting strength of racial [minorities]." …The theoretical basis for this type of impairment is that where minority and majority voters consistently prefer different candidates, the majority, by virtue of its numerical superiority, will regularly defeat the choices of minority voters. Multimember districts and at‑large voting schemes, however, are not per se violative of minority voters' rights.…Minority voters who contend that the multimember form of districting violates Section 2 must prove that the use of a multimember electoral structure operates to minimize or cancel out their ability to elect their preferred candidates.…[35]
First, the minority group must be able to demonstrate that it is sufficiently large and geographically compact to constitute a majority in a single‑member district.…Second, the minority group must be able to show that it is politically cohesive.…Third, the minority must be able to demonstrate that the white majority votes sufficiently as a bloc as to enable it—in the absence of special circumstances, such as the minority candidate running unopposed—usually to defeat the minority's preferred candidate.[36]
 In true disparate impact fashion, what counted for the Gingles majority was whether—not why—racial bloc voting diluted minority votes.[37] The Gingles rule is that, irrespective of intent, a voting district that has the effect of impermissibly diluting the voting strength of an identifiable minority group violates Section 2 and warrants affirmative relief. The three‑part Gingles test is not restricted to multimember systems, as in Gingles itself. It applies also in single‑member districts where the plaintiffs have achieved some representation, but claim that their ability to “elect representatives of their choice” has been diluted.[38] Significantly, Gingles indicated that difficulty in electing minority‑preferred candidates and the extent of racially polarized voting outweighed geographical compactness in importance.[39] This ruling enabled the ignoring of compactness in the creation of many new majority‑minority districts.
Gingles concluded that “the single‑member district is generally the appropriate standard” for minority representation[40] --a conclusion that triggered the courts and DOJ to promote creation of single‑member, majority‑minority districts. The resultant explosion of new majority‑minority districts augmented the constitutional dilemmas about racial gerrymandering.[41] Gingles gave rise to an ideological clash in the Court. In her Gingles concurrence, Justice O’Connor rejected the rationale of the ruling on the ground that it was tantamount to an endorsement of “rough” proportionality, which while “not quite the same as a right to strict proportionality…[is] inconsistent with Section 2’s disclaimer and with the results test that is codified in Section 2.”[42] O’Connor’s concern regarding proportionality remains to this day.
 Since the 1965 passage of the VRA, the number of African-American and Hispanic publicly -elected office holders has risen dramatically. At VRA’s onset, there were fewer than 100 elected Black officeholders in the Section 5-targeted states, and less than 200 nationwide. By 1990, these numbers had soared to 3,394 in these states, and 7,370 nationally.[43] In the  states with the greatest Hispanic populations—Arizona, California, Florida, New Mexico, New York, and Texas—the number of elected Latino officials rose from 1,280 in 1973 to 3,592 in 1990.[44] Nationwide, the number of Black and Hispanic officials increased from 3,063 to nearly 5,000 between 1984 and 1990 alone.[45] There were five African Americans and three Hispanics in the 1965 Congress. In 1996, there were seventeen Hispanics and thirty‑eight Blacks, a six and sevenfold increase.[46] A significant African American and Hispanic presence in public office has continued into the new millennium.[47]  For example, in states where African American and Hispanics constituted more than 10% in the year 2000 census, their state legislative office holding numbers rose significantly.[48] 
These impressive minority office-holding increases resulted, to a great degree, from the VRA-prompted package:  abolition of invidious voting tests; preclearance requirements; and expanded minority registrations; followed by increased minority voter turnout. But, even though Blacks and Hispanics have been elected where minorities were not a majority (think President Obama), a crucial factor has been the adoption of majority‑minority legislative districts.[49] For example, when fourteen Blacks and six Latinos came to Congress in 1992—the greatest absolute increase in Black representation ever in a single year—almost all of them were elected from majority‑minority districts drawn under Sections 2 and 5.[50]
In his Holder v. Hall (1993)[51] concurrence, Justice Clarence Thomas exposed many of the issues associated with the creation of majority districts and similar devices meant to increase the number of minority elected officials. These issues are serious ones and should be discussed by the public, but thus far the discussion has been largely restricted to a small group of scholars interested in voting rights. Excerpts from the Thomas opinion follow:
Only a "voting qualification or prerequisite to voting, or standard, practice, or procedure" can be challenged under § 2. . . . . In my view, however, the only principle limiting the scope of the terms "standard, practice, or procedure" that can be derived from the text of the Act would exclude . . .challenges to allegedly dilutive election methods that we have considered within the scope of the Act in the past. . . .
A review of the current state of our cases shows that by construing the Act to cover potentially dilutive electoral mechanisms, we have immersed the federal courts in a hopeless project of weighing questions of political theory -- questions judges must confront to establish a benchmark concept of an "undiluted" vote. Worse, in pursuing the ideal measure of voting strength, we have devised a remedial mechanism that encourages federal courts to segregate voters into racially designated districts to ensure minority electoral success. In doing so, we have collaborated in what may aptly be termed the racial "balkanization" of the Nation.
 If one surveys the history of the Voting Rights Act, 42 U.S.C. § 1973 et seq., one can only be struck by the sea change that has occurred in the application and enforcement of the Act since it was passed in 1965. The statute was originally perceived as a remedial provision directed specifically at eradicating discriminatory practices that restricted blacks' ability to register and vote in the segregated South. Now, the Act has grown into something entirely different. In construing the Act to cover claims of vote dilution, we have converted the Act into a device for regulating, rationing, and apportioning political power among racial and ethnic groups. In the process, we have read the Act essentially as a grant of authority to the federal judiciary to develop theories on basic principles of representative government, for it is only a resort to political theory that can enable a court to determine which electoral systems provide the "fairest" levels of representation or the most "effective" or "undiluted" votes to minorities. . . .
The Court's decision in Allen v. State Bd. of Elections, 393 U.S. 544 (1969), however, marked a fundamental shift in the focal point of the Act. . . . The decision in Allen thus ensured that the terms "standard, practice, or procedure" would extend to encompass a wide array of electoral practices or voting systems that might be challenged for reducing the potential impact of minority votes.
As a consequence, Allen also ensured that courts would be required to confront a number of complex and essentially political questions in assessing claims of vote dilution under the Voting Rights Act. . . . But in setting the benchmark of what "undiluted" or fully "effective" voting strength should be, a court must necessarily make some judgments based purely on an assessment of principles of political theory. As Justice Harlan pointed out in his dissent in Allen, the Voting Rights Act supplies no rule for a court to rely upon in deciding, for example, whether a multimember at-large system of election is to be preferred to a single-member district system; that is, whether one provides a more "effective" vote than another. "Under one system, Negroes have some influence in the election of all officers; under the other, minority groups have more influence in the selection of fewer officers." Allensupra, at 586. The choice is inherently a political one, and depends upon the selection of a theory for defining the fully "effective" vote -- at bottom, a theory for defining effective participation in representative government. In short, what a court is actually asked to do in a vote dilution case is "to choose among competing bases of representation -- ultimately, really, among competing theories of political philosophy." .
Perhaps the most prominent feature of the philosophy that has emerged in vote dilution decisions since Allen has been the Court's preference for single-member districting schemes, both as a benchmark for measuring undiluted minority voting strength and as a remedial mechanism for guaranteeing minorities undiluted voting power. Indeed, commentators surveying the history of voting rights litigation have concluded that it has been the objective of voting rights plaintiffs to use the Act to attack multimember districting schemes and to replace them with single-member districting systems drawn with majority-minority districts to ensure minority control of seats.
The obvious advantage the Court has perceived in single-member districts, of course, is their tendency to enhance the ability of any numerical minority in the electorate to gain control of seats in a representative body. But in choosing single-member districting as a benchmark electoral plan on that basis the Court has made a political decision and, indeed, a decision that itself depends on a prior political choice made in answer to Justice Harlan's question in Allen. Justice Harlan asked whether a  group's votes should be considered to be more "effective" when they provide influence over a greater number of seats, or control over a lesser number of seats. See 393 U.S.[544] at 586. In answering that query, the Court has determined that the purpose of the vote -- or of the fully "effective" vote -- is controlling seats. In other words, in an effort to develop standards for assessing claims of dilution, the Court has adopted the view that members of any numerically significant minority are denied a fully effective use of the franchise unless they are able to control seats in an elected body. 5 Under this theory, votes that do not control a representative are essentially wasted; those who cast them go unrepresented and are just as surely disenfranchised as if they had been barred from registering. Such conclusions, of course, depend upon a certain theory of the "effective" vote, a theory that is not inherent in the concept of representative democracy itself. 6
In fact, it should be clear that the assumptions that have guided the Court reflect only one possible understanding of effective exercise of the franchise, an understanding based on the view that voters are "represented" only when they choose a delegate who will mirror their views in the legislative halls. See generally H. Pitkin, The Concept of Representation 60-91 (1967). 7 But it is certainly possible to construct a theory of effective political participation that would accord greater importance to voters' ability to influence, rather than control, elections. And especially in a two-party system such as ours, the influence of a potential "swing" group of voters composing 10% to 20% of the electorate in a given district can be considerable. 8 Even such a focus on practical influence, however, is not a necessary component of the definition of the "effective" vote. Some conceptions of representative government may primarily emphasize the formal value of the vote as a mechanism for participation in the electoral process, whether it results in control of a seat or not. Under such a theory, minorities unable to control elected posts would not be considered essentially without a vote; rather, a vote duly cast and counted would be deemed just as "effective" as any other. If a minority group is unable to control seats, that result may plausibly be attributed to the inescapable fact that, in a majoritarian system, numerical minorities lose elections. . . .
Once one accepts the proposition that the effectiveness of votes is measured in terms of the control of seats, the core of any vote dilution claim is an assertion that the group in question is unable to control the "proper" number of seats -- that is, the number of seats that the minority's percentage of the population would enable it to control in the benchmark "fair" system. The claim is inherently based on ratios between the numbers of the minority in the population and the numbers of seats controlled. As Justice O’Connor has noted, "any theory of vote dilution must necessarily rely to some extent on a measure of minority voting strength that makes some reference to the proportion between the minority group and the electorate at large."Gingles, 478 U.S. [30]at 84. As a result, only a mathematical calculation can answer the fundamental question posed by a claim of vote dilution. And once again, in selecting the proportion that will be used to define the undiluted strength of a minority the ratio that will provide the principle for decision in a vote dilution case -- a court must make a political choice.
The ratio for which this Court has opted, and thus the mathematical principle driving the results in our cases, is undoubtedly direct proportionality. . . .
The dabbling in political theory that dilution cases have prompted, however, is hardly the worst aspect of our vote dilution jurisprudence. Far more pernicious has been the Court's willingness to accept the one underlying premise that must inform every minority vote dilution claim: the assumption that the group asserting dilution is not merely a racial or ethnic group, but a group having distinct political interests as well. Of necessity, in resolving vote dilution actions we have given credence to the view that race defines political interest. We have acted on the implicit assumption that members of racial and ethnic groups must all think alike on important matters of public policy and must have their own "minority preferred" representatives holding seats in elected bodies if they are to be considered represented at all.
It is true that in Gingles we stated that whether a racial group is "politically cohesive" may not be assumed, but rather must be proved in each case. See 478 U.S.[30] at 51, 56. But the standards we have employed for determining political cohesion have proved so insubstantial that this "precondition" does not present much of a barrier to the assertion of vote dilution claims on behalf of any racial group. Moreover, it provides no test -- indeed, it is not designed to provide a test -- of whether race itself determines a distinctive political community of interest. According to the rule adopted in Gingles, plaintiffs must show simply that members of a racial group tend to prefer the same candidates. See 478 U.S.[30] at 61-67. There is no set standard defining how strong the correlation must be. . . .
As a result, Gingles' requirement of proof of political cohesiveness, as practically applied, has proved little different from a working assumption that racial groups can be conceived of largely as political interest groups. And operating under that assumption, we have assigned federal courts the task of ensuring that minorities are assured their "just" share of seats in elected bodies throughout the Nation.
To achieve that result through the currently fashionable mechanism of drawing majority-minority single-member districts, we have embarked upon what has been aptly characterized as a process of "creating racially 'safe boroughs.'” We have involved the federal courts, and indeed the Nation, in the enterprise of systematically dividing the country into electoral districts along racial lines -- an enterprise of segregating the races into political homelands that amounts, in truth, to nothing short of a system of "political apartheid." Blacks are drawn into "black districts" and given "black representatives"; Hispanics are drawn into Hispanic districts and given "Hispanic representatives"; and so on. Worse still, it is not only the courts that have taken up this project. In response to judicial decisions and the promptings of the Justice Department, the States themselves, in an attempt to avoid costly and disruptive Voting Rights Act litigation, have begun to gerrymander electoral districts according to race. . . .
 The assumptions upon which our vote dilution decisions have been based should be repugnant to any nation that strives for the ideal of a color-blind Constitution. "The principle of equality is at war with the notion that District A must be represented by a Negro, as it is with the notion that District B must be represented by a Caucasian, District C by a Jew, District D by a Catholic, and so on." Wright v. Rockefeller, 376 U.S. 52, 66 (1964) (Douglas, J., dissenting). Despite Justice Douglas' warning sounded 30 years ago, our voting rights decisions are rapidly progressing toward a system that is indistinguishable in principle from a scheme under which members of different racial groups are divided into separate electoral registers and allocated a proportion of political power on the basis of race. Under our jurisprudence, rather than requiring registration on racial rolls and dividing power purely on a population basis, we have simply resorted to the somewhat less precise expedient of drawing geographic district lines to capture minority populations and to ensure the existence of the "appropriate" number of "safe minority seats."
That distinction in the practical implementation of the concept, of course, is immaterial. 14 The basic premises underlying our system of safe minority districts and those behind the racial register are the same: that members of the racial group must think alike and that their interests are so distinct that the group must be provided a separate body of representatives in the legislature to voice its unique point of view. Such a "system, by whatever name it is called, is a divisive force in a community, emphasizing differences between candidates and voters that are irrelevant."  Justice Douglas correctly predicted the results of state sponsorship of such a theory of representation: "When racial or religious lines are drawn by the State, . . . antagonisms that relate to race or to religion rather than to political issues are generated; communities seek not the best representative but the best racial or religious partisan." Id., at 67. In short, few devices could be better designed to exacerbate racial tensions than the consciously segregated districting system currently being constructed in the name of the Voting Rights Act.
As a practical political matter, our drive to segregate political districts by race can only serve to deepen racial divisions by destroying any need for voters or candidates to build bridges between racial groups or to form voting coalitions. "Black-preferred" candidates are assured election in "safe black districts"; white-preferred candidates are assured election in "safe white districts." Neither group needs to draw on support from the other's constituency to win on election day. As one judge described the current trend of voting rights cases: "We are bent upon polarizing political subdivisions by race. The arrangement we construct makes it unnecessary, and probably unwise, for an elected official from a white majority district to be responsive at all to the wishes of black citizens; similarly, it is politically unwise for a black official from a black majority district to be responsive at all to white citizens."
As this description suggests, the system we have instituted affirmatively encourages a racially based understanding of the representative function. The clear premise of the system is that geographic districts are merely a device to be manipulated to establish "black representatives" whose real constituencies are defined, not in terms of the voters who populate their districts, but in terms of race. The "black representative's" function, in other words, is to represent the "black interest.". . .
In my view, our current practice should not continue. Not for another Term, not until the next case, not for another day.

Remembering Adlai Stevenson and the Morality of Consent[52]
Abolishing the affirmative action dimensions of the VRA and their assumption of White racist and ethnic venom would be a way of conforming to the Thomas critique recited above. It has been argued here that the majority opinion in Shelby County v. Holder abolished the White-venom rationale of affirmative action for minority voting. It follows that the VRA should be restricted to prohibiting that which can be solidly proven (and not assumed) to be an intentional effort to block minority voting? Of course the scope of the VRA is debatable. For example, the four-member minority dissent in Shelby County v. Holder  (2013) lamented (over 37 pages),[53] that there still exists an amplitude of antiminority animosity that disallowed any change in Section 5, yet alone Section 2. Of course,  the public should be concerned with whether Justice Thomas’ provocative critique should be adhered to. But we get little help from the Obama Administration which has insisted upon the expansion of transparent government. That Administration has not publicized the racial/ethnic Balkanization dimensions of the VRA, and has not helped the public evaluate the merits of the federal antidilution-voing  thrust.
At this juncture, Adlai Stevenson’s acceptance of the presidential nomination in 1952 should be recalled. “Let’s face it. Let’s talk sense to the American people.” Let us storm walls of ignorance through truth, courage and morality, “contemptuous of lies, half truths, circuses and demagoguery.”[54] A 1996 persuasive social science-survey on the subject tells us that the American people as a whole are generally distrustful of and opposed to affirmative action[55]-- all the more reason for our political leaders to vent critical voting-rights issues. If a majority opposes VRA’s affirmative action, this attitude might be changed through a thoughtful discussion of the issues led by our political leaders. Democratic theory holds that there is a great morality to majoritarian consent and dissent. Informed majoritarianism should help remedy the “disappointing” unprofessionalism and “deep ideological polarization” which the DOJ’s Inspector General found in the DOJ’s Voting Rights Section of the Civil Rights Division—a Section which administers the VRA.[56]Among the issues of the VRA that should be publicly discussed are:
·         Has White America really changed in terms of allowing nonwhites to vote and participate in political activities as they see fit. Or is this political activity badly impeded by White antiminority attitudes?
·         Is it socially desirable for government to create legislative districts based on a population’s color or ethnicity?
·         Do minorities require minority office-holding to be afforded good government?
·         Should forbidden discrimination be assumed through statistical analysis as disparate-impact theory allows? Should not the demonstration of invidious antiminority animosity be required?
·         Does not the VRA Section 203 requirement of providing voting materials in non-English languages to language minorities undercut social cohesiveness? Should not literacy in English be required?
·         It is difficult to imagine any voting impediments (e.g., photo ID’s; prohibitions against felons from voting; standing in long voting lines) that do not disproportionately affect minorities and diminish their voting capacities. What should the VRA prohibit?

   Copyright © 2013 by William M. Leiter. All Rights Reserved.




[1] Slip Opinion, No. 12-96 , June 25, 2013. Available at http://www.supremecourt.gov/opinions/12pdf/12-96_6k47.pdf
[2] Codified as amended at 42 USC § 1973 et  seq.
[3] Id.
[4] Shelby  County v. Holder, Slip Opinion, No. 12-96 (2013). Available at http://www.supremecourt.gov/opinions/12pdf/12-96_6k47.pdf
[5] Id, Majority Opinion at 3-5.
[6] Id, Majority Opinion at 3-5.
[7] Id, Majority Opinion at 24. Italics and bolding added.
[8] Id, Majority Opinion at 13-15. Internal citations omitted.
[11] 396 U.S. 544.
[12] Allen v. Board of Elections, 393 U.S. 544.
[13] David Lublin, The Paradox of Representation  (Princeton U. Press, 1997), 5-6.
[14] Id. at 6, 28-29.
[15] Kathryn Abrams, Raising Politics Up, 63 NYU L. Rev. 449, 470-471 n139 (1988).
[16] Lublin, Paradox of Representation at 6, 7, 28 (cited in note 13).
[17] Abigail Thernstrom, Voting Rights and Wrongs, The Elusive Quest for Racially Fair Elections (AEI Press, 2009), 8 and passim.
[19] U.S. Department of Justice, Attorney General Eric Holder Speaks at the Lyndon Baines Johnson Library & Museum, Austin, TX, Tuesday, December 13, 2011. Available at http://www.justice.gov/iso/opa/ag/speeches/2011/ag-speech-111213.html
[20] Cited in Jerry Marken & Krissan Thompson, Holder Joins Debate On Voting Laws’ Turnout Effect, Washington Post, Suburban Edition,  December 13, 2011, A-Section, p. A02.
[21] U.S. Department of Justice, Attorney General Eric Holder Speaks at the Lyndon Baines Johnson Library & Museum, Austin, TX, Tuesday, December 13, 2011. Available at http://www.justice.gov/iso/opa/ag/speeches/2011/ag-speech-111213.html ; Thomas Perez, U.S. Enforcement of the Voting Rights Act, 64 Rutgers L. Rev. 939, Summer 2012, 943.
[23] Nathaniel Persily, Drawing Lines in Shifting Sands: The DOJ, the VRA, and the 2011 Redistricting Process, 23 Stan. L. & Pol’y Rev. 345 (2012), p 357.  
[24]  Letter from U.S. Assistant Attorney General to Deputy Assistant South Carolina Attorney General  on South Carolina Voter Identification, December 23, 2011.Available at http://www.justice.gov/crt/about/vot/sec_5/ltr/l_122311.php
[25] Letter from U.S. Assistant Attorney General to Texas Director of Elections, March 12, 2012. Available at http://www.justice.gov/crt/about/vot/sec_5/ltr/l_031212.php
[26] U.S. Department of Justice, Guidance Concerning Redistricting, 27 Federal Register No. 27, February 27, 2011. http://www.justice.gov/crt/about/vot/sec_5/sec5guidance2011.pdf
[27] See endnotes 50, 51 for references on this point.
[28]  Persily, Drawing Lines in Shifting Sands, 23 Stan. L. & Pol’y Rev. 345 (2012), 357 (cited in note 23).
[29]  Texas v. U.S., The U.S Opening Trial Brief, U.S. District Court, D.C. January 13, 2012, 2, 4-5.
[30] Letter from U.S. Acting Assistant Attorney General to James Cauley, Objection to Kinston’s Nonpartisan Elections, August 17, 2009. Available at http://www.justice.gov/crt/about/vot/sec_5/ltr/l_081709.php

[32] Charlie Savage, U.S is Suing in Texas Cases Over Voting By Minorities, New York Times, Aug, 23, 2012, National Ed, p. A12.
[33] 478 U.S. 30.
[34] Id. at 48, and ns 15, 49.
[35] Id. at 47.
[36] Id. at 50-51(emphasis added).
[37] Editors’ Notes and Questions on Gingles in Samuel Issacharoff, Pamela Karlan, and Richard Pildes, eds, The Law of Democracy (Foundation, 1998), 464, 466.
[38] See Johnson v. DeGrandy, 512 U.S. 997, 1008; Editors’ Notes on Section 2 in Issacharoff, Karlan, and Pildes, Law of Democracy, 499-500, 506-509 (cited above).

[39] Thornburg v. Gingles, 478 U.S. 30 (1986), 44, 49n17.
[40] Id. at 50 n17
[41] Alexander Keysaar, The Right to Vote (Basic Books, 2000), 294; David Lublin, The Paradox of Representation (Princeton, 1997), 30.
[42] Thornburg v. Gingles, 478 U.S. 30, 96.
[43] Pei-te Lien, The Voting Rights Act and its Implications for Three NonBlack Minorities, 140-143 in Richard M. Valelly ed, The Voting Rights Act: Securing the Ballot (Congressional Quarterly Press, 2006).
[44] Id.
[45] Keith J. Bybee, Mistaken Identity (Princeton U Press, 1998) 28.
[46] David Lublin, The Paradox of Representation (Princeton U Press, 1997), 22.
[47] Abigail Thernstrom, Voting Rights and Wrongs, The Elusive Quest for Racially Fair Elections (AEI Press, 2009), 11.
[48] David Lublin, et al, Has the Voting Rights Act Outlived Its Usefulness? In a Word,“No,” 34 Legislative Studies Quarterly 525 (November, 2009), 529.
[49] David Lublin, Paradox of Representation, 23-24 (Princeton U Press, 1997); Laughlin McDonald, The 1982 Amendments in Bernard Grofman & Chandler Davidson, eds, Controversies in Minority Voting (Brookings, 1992) at 73-74.
[50] Keith J. Bybee, Mistaken Identity, 29 (Princeton U Press, 1998).
[51] 512 U.S. 874, 893ff. Most citations and footnotes omitted.
[52] Morality concept from title of Alexander M. Bickel’s book, The Morality of Consent (Yale Press, 1975).
[54] Adlai E. Stevenson, Major Campaign Speeches of Adlai E. Stevenson, 1952, Random House, 1953), 10.
[55] Donald R. Kinder and Lynn Sanders, Divided by Color (U Chicago press, 1996).
[56] Cited by Charlie Savage, Report Finds Political Splits and Unprofessionalism in Voting Agency, New York Times, National Edition, March 13, 2013, p A16. For entire report, see http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2013/s1303.pdf

No comments:

Post a Comment